Vaisheshika or VaiÅeá¹£ika (Sanskrit: वà¥à¤¶à¥à¤·à¤¿à¤) is one of the six orthodox schools of Hinduism (Vedic systems) from ancient India. In its early stages, the VaiÅeá¹£ika was an independent philosophy with its own metaphysics, epistemology, logic, ethics, and soteriology. Over time, the VaiÅeá¹£ika system became similar in its philosophical procedures, ethical conclusions and soteriology to the NyÄya school of Hinduism, but retained its difference in epistemology and metaphysics.
The epistemology of VaiÅeá¹£ika school of Hinduism, like Buddhism, accepted only two reliable means to knowledge - perception and inference. VaiÅeá¹£ika school and Buddhism both consider their respective scriptures as indisputable and valid means to knowledge, the difference being that the scriptures held to be a valid and reliable source by VaiÅeá¹£ikas were the Vedas.
Vaisheshika school is known for its insights in naturalism, and it is a form of atomism in natural philosophy. It postulated that all objects in the physical universe are reducible to paramÄá¹u (atoms), and one's experiences are derived from the interplay of substance (a function of atoms, their number and their spatial arrangements), quality, activity, commonness, particularity and inherence. Knowledge and liberation was achievable by complete understanding of the world of experience, according to VaiÅeá¹£ika school of Hinduism.
VaiÅeá¹£ika darshana was founded by Kaá¹Äda Kashyapa around the 2nd century BC.
Overview
Although the Vaisheshika system developed independently from the Nyaya school of Hinduism, the two became similar and are often studied together. In its classical form, however, the Vaishesika school differed from the Nyaya in one crucial respect: where Nyaya accepted four sources of valid knowledge, the Vaishesika accepted only two.
The epistemology of VaiÅeá¹£ika school of Hinduism accepted only two reliable means to knowledge - perception and inference.
Vaisheshika espouses a form of atomism, that the reality is composed of four substances (earth, water, air, fire). Each of these four are of two types, explains Ganeri, atomic (paramÄá¹u) and composite. An atom is that which is indestructible (anitya), indivisible, and has a special kind of dimension, called âsmallâ (aá¹u). A composite is that which is divisible into atoms. Whatever human beings perceive is composite, and even the smallest perceptible thing, namely, a fleck of dust, has parts, which are therefore invisible. The VaiÅeá¹£ikas visualized the smallest composite thing as a âtriadâ (tryaá¹uka) with three parts, each part with a âdyadâ (dyaá¹uka). VaiÅeá¹£ikas believed that a dyad has two parts, each of which is an atom. Size, form, truths and everything that human beings experience as a whole is a function of atoms, their number and their spatial arrangements.
Vaisheshika postulated that what one experiences is derived from dravya (substance: a function of atoms, their number and their spatial arrangements), guna (quality), karma (activity), samanya (commonness), vishesha (particularity) and samavaya (inherence, inseparable connectedness of everything).
Epistemology
Hinduism identifies six Pramanas as epistemically reliable means to accurate knowledge and to truths: Pratyaká¹£a (perception), AnumÄá¹a (inference), UpamÄá¹a (comparison and analogy), ArthÄpatti (postulation, derivation from circumstances), Anupalabdi (non-perception, negative/cognitive proof) and Åabda (word, testimony of past or present reliable experts). Of these VaiÅeá¹£ika epistemology considered only pratyaká¹£a (perception) and anumÄna (inference) as reliable means of valid knowledge. Nyaya school, related to VaiÅeá¹£ika, accepts four out of these six.
- Pratyaká¹£a (पà¥à¤°à¤¤à¥à¤¯à¤à¥à¤·) means perception. It is of two types: external and internal. External perception is described as that arising from the interaction of five senses and worldly objects, while internal perception is described by this school as that of inner sense, the mind. The ancient and medieval texts of Hinduism identify four requirements for correct perception: Indriyarthasannikarsa (direct experience by one's sensory organ(s) with the object, whatever is being studied), Avyapadesya (non-verbal; correct perception is not through hearsay, according to ancient Indian scholars, where one's sensory organ relies on accepting or rejecting someone else's perception), Avyabhicara (does not wander; correct perception does not change, nor is it the result of deception because one's sensory organ or means of observation is drifting, defective, suspect) and Vyavasayatmaka (definite; correct perception excludes judgments of doubt, either because of one's failure to observe all the details, or because one is mixing inference with observation and observing what one wants to observe, or not observing what one does not want to observe). Some ancient scholars proposed "unusual perception" as pramana and called it internal perception, a proposal contested by other Indian scholars. The internal perception concepts included pratibha (intuition), samanyalaksanapratyaksa (a form of induction from perceived specifics to a universal), and jnanalaksanapratyaksa (a form of perception of prior processes and previous states of a 'topic of study' by observing its current state). Further, the texts considered and refined rules of accepting uncertain knowledge from Pratyaká¹£a-pranama, so as to contrast nirnaya (definite judgment, conclusion) from anadhyavasaya (indefinite judgment).
- AnumÄá¹a (ठनà¥à¤®à¤¾à¤¨) means inference. It is described as reaching a new conclusion and truth from one or more observations and previous truths by applying reason. Observing smoke and inferring fire is an example of Anumana. In all except one Hindu philosophies, this is a valid and useful means to knowledge. The method of inference is explained by Indian texts as consisting of three parts: pratijna (hypothesis), hetu (a reason), and drshtanta (examples). The hypothesis must further be broken down into two parts, state the ancient Indian scholars: sadhya (that idea which needs to proven or disproven) and paksha (the object on which the sadhya is predicated). The inference is conditionally true if sapaksha (positive examples as evidence) are present, and if vipaksha (negative examples as counter-evidence) are absent. For rigor, the Indian philosophies also state further epistemic steps. For example, they demand Vyapti - the requirement that the hetu (reason) must necessarily and separately account for the inference in "all" cases, in both sapaksha and vipaksha. A conditionally proven hypothesis is called a nigamana (conclusion).
Syllogism
The syllogism of the VaiÅeá¹£ika school was similar to that of the NyÄya school of Hinduism, but the names given by PraÅastapÄda to the 5 members of syllogism are different.
Literature of Vaisheshika
The earliest systematic exposition of the Vaisheshika is found in the VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tra of Kaá¹Äda (or Kaá¹abhaksha). This treatise is divided into ten books. The two commentaries on the VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tra, RÄvaá¹abhÄá¹£ya and BhÄradvÄjavá¹tti are no more extant. PraÅastapÄdaâs PadÄrthadharmasaá¹graha (c. 4th century) is the next important work of this school. Though commonly known as bhÄá¹£ya of VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tra, this treatise is basically an independent work on the subject. The next Vaisheshika treatise, Candraâs DaÅapadÄrthaÅÄstra (648) based on PraÅastapÄdaâs treatise is available only in Chinese translation. The earliest commentary available on PraÅastapÄdaâs treatise is VyomaÅivaâs VyomavatÄ« (8th century). The other three commentaries are Åridharaâs NyÄyakandalÄ« (991), Udayanaâs KiranÄvali (10th century) and Årivatsaâs LÄ«lÄvatÄ« (11th century). ÅivÄdityaâs SaptapadÄrthÄ« which also belongs to the same period, presents the NyÄya and the VaiÅeá¹£ika principles as a part of one whole. Åaá¹kara MiÅraâs UpaskÄra on VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tra is also an important work.
The Categories or PadÄrtha
According to the Vaisheshika school, all things which exist, which can be cognised, and which can be named are padÄrthas (literal meaning: the meaning of a word), the objects of experience. All objects of experience can be classified into six categories, dravya (substance), guá¹a (quality), karma (activity), sÄmÄnya (generality), viÅeá¹£a (particularity) and samavÄya (inherence). Later VaiÅeá¹£ikas (ÅrÄ«dhara and Udayana and ÅivÄditya) added one more category abhava (non-existence). The first three categories are defined as artha (which can perceived) and they have real objective existence. The last three categories are defined as budhyapeká¹£am (product of intellectual discrimination) and they are logical categories.
1.Dravya (substance): The substances are conceived as 9 in number. They are, pá¹thvÄ« (earth), ap (water), tejas (fire), vÄyu (air), ÄkaÅa (ether), kÄla (time), dik (space), Ätman (self or soul) and manas (mind). The first five are called bhÅ«tas, the substances having some specific qualities so that they could be perceived by one or the other external senses.
2.Guá¹a (quality): The VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tra mentions 17 guá¹as (qualities), to which PraÅastapÄda added another 7. While a substance is capable of existing independently by itself, a guá¹a(quality) cannot exist so. The original 17 guá¹as (qualities) are, rÅ«pa (colour), rasa (taste), gandha (smell), sparÅa (touch), saá¹khyÄ (number), parimÄá¹a (size/dimension/quantity), pá¹thaktva (individuality), saá¹yoga (conjunction/accompaniments), vibhÄga (disjunction), paratva (priority), aparatva (posteriority), buddhi (knowledge), sukha (pleasure), duḥkha (pain), icchÄ (desire), dveá¹£a (aversion) and prayatna (effort). To these PraÅastapÄda added gurutva (heaviness), dravatva (fluidity), sneha (viscosity), dharma (merit), adharma (demerit), Åabda (sound) and saá¹skÄra (faculty).
3.Karma (activity): The karmas (activities) like guá¹as (qualities) have no separate existence, they belong to the substances. But while a quality is a permanent feature of a substance, an activity is a transient one. ÄkÄÅa (ether), kÄla (time), dik (space) and Ätman (self), though substances, are devoid of karma (activity).
4.SÄmÄnya (generality): Since there are plurality of substances, there will be relations among them. When a property is found common to many substances, it is called sÄmÄnya.
5.ViÅeá¹£a (particularity): By means of viÅeá¹£a, we are able to perceive substances as different from one another. As the ultimate atoms are innumerable so are the viÅeá¹£as.
6.SamavÄya (inherence): Kaá¹Äda defined samavÄya as the relation between the cause and the effect. PraÅastapÄda defined it as the relationship existing between the substances that are inseparable, standing to one another in the relation of the container and the contained. The relation of samavÄya is not perceivable but only inferable from the inseparable connection of the substances.
The atomic theory
The early VaiÅeá¹£ika texts presented the following syllogism to prove that all objects i.e. the four bhÅ«tas, pá¹thvÄ« (earth), ap (water), tejas (fire) and vÄyu (air) are made of indivisible paramÄá¹us (atoms): Assume that the matter is not made of indivisible atoms, and that it is continuous. Take a stone. One can divide this up into infinitely many pieces (since matter is continuous). Now, the Himalayan mountain range also has infinitely many pieces, so one may build another Himalayan mountain range with the infinite number of pieces that one has. One begins with a stone and ends up with the Himalayas, which is a paradox - so the original assumption that matter is continuous must be wrong, and so all objects must be made up of a finite number of paramÄá¹us (atoms).
According to the VaiÅeá¹£ika school, the trasareá¹u (dust particles visible in the sunbeam coming through a small window hole) are the smallest mahat (perceivable) particles and defined as tryaá¹ukas (triads). These are made of three parts, each of which are defined as dvyaá¹uka (dyad). The dvyaá¹ukas are conceived as made of two parts, each of which are defined as paramÄá¹u (atom). The paramÄá¹us (atoms) are indivisible and eternal, they can neither be created nor destroyed. Each paramÄá¹u (atom) possesses its own distinct viÅeá¹£a (individuality).
The measure of the partless atoms is known as parimaá¹á¸ala parimÄá¹a. It is eternal and it cannot generate the measure of any other substance. Its measure is its own absolutely.
Later developments
Over the centuries, the school became closely identified with the Nyaya school of Indian philosophy, as nyÄya-vaiÅeá¹£ika.
The school suffered a natural decline in India after the 15th century.
Views by the Vedanta School
The Vaisheshikas say that the visible universe is created from an original stock of atoms (janim asataḥ). As Kaá¹Äda's VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tra (7.1.26) states, nityaá¹ parimaá¹á¸alam (that which is of the smallest size, the atom, is eternal), he and his followers also postulate eternality for other, nonatomic entities, including the souls who become embodied, and even a Supreme Soul. But in VaiÅeá¹£ika cosmology the souls and the Supersoul play only token roles in the atomic production of the universe. The Brahma Sutra (2.2.12) says ubhayathÄpi na karmatas tad-abhavaḥ. According to this sÅ«tra, one cannot claim that, at the time of creation, atoms first combine together because they are impelled by some karmic impulse adhering in the atoms themselves, since atoms by themselves, in their primeval state before combining into complex objects, have no ethical responsibility that might lead them to acquire pious and sinful reactions. Nor can the initial combination of atoms be explained as a result of the residual karma of the living entities who lie dormant prior to creation, since these reactions are each jiva's own and cannot be transferred from them even to other jÄ«vas, what to speak of inert atoms.
See also
- Darshanas
- Hindu philosophy
- Hinduism
- Nyaya (philosophy)
- PadÄrtha
- VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tra
- Atomism
- Naturalism (philosophy)
Notes
References
- Chattopadhyaya, D. (1986), Indian Philosophy: A Popular Introduction, Peopleâs Publishing House, New Delhi, ISBNÂ 81-7007-023-6Â .
- Dasgupta, Surendranath (1975), A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, ISBN 81-208-0412-8Â .
- Radhakrishnan, S. (2006), Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, Oxford University Press, New Delhi, ISBNÂ 0-19-563820-4Â .
Further reading
- Bimal Matilal (1977), A History of Indian Literature - NyÄya-VaiÅeá¹£ika, Otto Harrassowitz Verlag, ISBN 978-3447018074, OCLCÂ 489575550
- Gopi Kaviraj (1961), Gleanings from the history and bibliography of the Nyaya-Vaisesika literature, Indian Studies: Past & Present, Volume 2, Number 4, OCLCÂ 24469380
External links
- A summary of Vaisheshika physics
- Shastra Nethralaya - Vaisheshika
- GRETIL e-text of the VaiÅeá¹£ika SÅ«tras